Tags: |
---|
Against the Unaccusative Analysis of Reflexives
Reinhart and Siloni argue that reflexives should be analyzed as
unergatives (i.e., the subject is not an underlying object). Under
their account, a "reduction" operation is applied to the reflexive
verb, which merges the two roles, and eliminates the verb's
accusative/dative case feature. Thus, the verb is left with a single
role (the external role), which is assigned to the subject.
(The subject's case is checked by infl). The reduction operation can
be applied either in lexicon, or in the syntax (at LF). Reinhart and
Siloni claim that this difference in the module where reduction
applies accounts for differences between how reflexives pattern in
different languages. E.g., reduction applies in syntax in French
(which has productive reflexives, and can apply reflexives to ECM
verbs); but applies in the lexicon in Hebrew or English (which have
non-productive reflexives, and can't apply reflexives to ECM
verbs).
Reinhart and Siloni begin the article by presenting arguments against a simple unergative account for reflexives: that reflexives are basically just transitives; and that the reflexive clitic originated as the object. E.g., "Jean se lave" would have the DS structure "[Jean [lave se]]." But this analysis seems untennable, given the numerous ways in which "Jean se lave" and "Jean le lave" seem to operate different symantically.
But Reinhart and Siloni point out that this is not the only
unergative account for reflexives, and go on to give their
reduction-based account. They impose a restriction on reduction, to
help account for the distribution of reflexives: it must apply to a
pair of free co--roles, one of which is external.
They then go on to discuss the unaccusative account, and present some problems with it. In particular, they claim that it's coverage is no better than their account; and show several ways in which reflexives pattern with unergatives (and not with unaccusatives). For example, you can make agent nominals from unergatives ("he is a good runner") and reflexives ("he is a good dresser") but not unaccusatives ("he is a good mover"). (But c.f. "The plant appears to be a good grower and producer.", found via google.)
Finally, they argue that reduction applies in the lexicon in some languages, and in the syntax in others. In particular, they use this to account for the productivity of reflexives, and for whether it can occur in ECM constructions:
- Jean se considere intellegent
Where the two merged roles come from two different verbs
(external
from consider, internal from intellegent).
Bibtex
@Unpublished{reinhart1999, author = {Tanya Reinhart, Tal Siloni}, title = {Against the Unaccusative Analysis of Reflexives}, note = {to appear in Studies on Unaccusativity: the Syntax-Lexicon Interface, CUP.}, year = 1999 }